Axioms and Theorems
5.1 Euclid's Axioms
In addition to the great practical value of Euclidean Geometry, the
ancient Greeks also found great esthetic value in the study of geometry.
Much as children assemble a few kinds blocks into many varied towers, mathematicians
assemble a few definitions and assumptions into many varied theorems. The
blocks are assembled with Hands, the axioms are assembled with Reason.
All of Euclidean Geometry (the thousands of theorems) were all put together
with a few different kinds of blocks. These are called "Euclid's
five axioms":
-
A-1 Every two points lie on exactly one line.
-
A-2 Any line segment with given endpoints may be continued in either
direction.
-
A-3 It is possible to construct a circle with any point as its center
and with a radius of any length. (This implies that there is neither
an upper nor lower limit to distance. In-other-words, any distance, no
mater how large can always be increased, and any distance, no mater how
small can always be divided.)
-
A-4 If two lines cross such that a pair of adjacent angles are congruent,
then each of these angles are also congruent to any other angle formed
in the same way.
-
A-5 (Parallel Axiom): Given a line l and a point not on l,
there is one and only one line which contains the point, and is parallel
to l.
In addition to these axioms, Euclidean Geometry is based on a number
of Common Notions or rules of logic that Euclid listed in "The Elements":
-
CN-1 Things which are equal to the same thing are also equal
to one another.
-
CN-2 If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal.
-
CN-3 If equals be subtracted from equals, the remainders are
equal.
-
CN-4 Things which coincide with one another are equal to one
another.
-
CN-5 The whole is greater than the part.
Euclid's goal was for these axioms and common notions to be (1) few in
number, and (2) so obviously true that they could not possible be argued
with. For over 2000 years many mathematicians believed that the fifth
axiom (the Parallel Axiom) was not needed. They believed that it could
instead be proved as a theorem of the first four axioms. There were numerous
attempts to do so. Early in the nineteenth century, three men working independently,
finally put an end to this impossible search. These men were Ivanovitch
Lobachevski in Russia, Karl Gauss in Germany, and János Bolyai in
Hungary. These men each developed theorems using Euclid's first four
axioms and a negation of the Parallel Axiom. Their expectation was
to eventually develop two theorems which contradicted each other.
This would prove that their negation of the Parallel Axiom is inconsistent
with the first four axioms - thereby proving the Parallel Axiom (and making
it the Parallel Theorem). To their surprise, however, they never obtained
a contradiction. Instead, they developed a complete and consistent geometry
- a non-Euclidean Geometry that is now called Hyperbolic Geometry.
This proved that the Parallel Axiom could not be derived from the other
four. This was of great mathematical and philosophical interest.
From the time of the Greeks, it was believed that geometric theorems were
such pure and perfect Truth that they did not need to be scrutinized by
observations of the real world. Now, those statements are only true
is some geometries. The only reason to prefer one geometry over another
is by comparison to the real world - a heavy blow to a geometor.
In the early twentieth century, Albert Einstein developed The General Theory
of Relativity which made extensive use of Hyperbolic Geometry. This
abstract, mathematical philosophical was now firmly in the realm of Science.
There are actually two ways to negate the Euclidean Parallel Axiom:
-
A-5S (Spherical Geometry Parallel Axiom): Given a line l and
a point not on l, no lines exist that contain the point,
and are parallel to l.
-
A-5H (Hyperbolic Geometry Parallel Axiom): Given a line l
and a point not on l, there are at least two distinct lines
which contains the point, and are parallel to l.
When thinking about these parallel axioms, it is important to remember
that "parallel" does not mean "lines that look like train tracks".
"Parallel" means two lines in the same plane that, no matter how far extended,
do not intersect.
The Spherical Geometry Parallel Axiom is inconsistent with Euclid's
first four axioms. In Spherical Geometry, The "lines" are great
circles. Most pairs of points (A and B) in Spherical Geometry, lie
on one and only one great circle; however if A and B happen to be antipodal
(on opposite ends of any single axis), then there are an infinite number
of different great circles that pass through them. This violates
Euclid's first axiom. Euclid's second axiom, "any line segment
with given endpoints may be continued in either direction" is also violated.
In Spherical Geometry, if points the endpoints of a line segment are moved
farther and farther apart, then they will eventually coincide.
Contrary to Lobachevski's, Bolyai's, and Gauss' expectations, the Hyperbolic
Geometry Parallel Axiom is perfectly consistent with Euclid's first four
axioms. And what a beautiful world this surprise opened up.
5.2 Betweeness and SAS Axioms:
In addition to the axioms and common notions that Euclid included in
"The Elements", he unknowingly made a number of implicit assumptions.
One of these is called the Betweeness Axiom and can be stated: "Of any
three points on a line, exactly one is between the other two."
Another is called the SAS (or Side-Angle-Side) Axiom.
The SAS axiom states that if two sides and the included angle of one
triangle are congruent to two sides and an included angle of a second triangle,
then the two triangles are congruent.
In "The Elements", Euclid presents what he believed to be a proof for
SAS:[Health-56]
Given:
ΔABC and ΔDEF,
with sides AB ≅ DE, side AC ≅ DF, and ∠A ≅ ∠D.
Proof:
Move ΔABC such that point A coincides with
point D, and line AB coincides with DE.
Point B will coincide with E, because AB ≅ DE.
Also, segment AC will coincide with DF, because ∠A ≅ ∠D.
Point C will coincide with F, because AC ≅ DF.
Line BC will coincide with EF, because two lines cannot enclose a space.
Finally, side BC is congruent to side EF, because the lines and endpoints
of each coincide.
Therefore, ∠B ≅ ∠E,
∠C ≅ ∠F, and
ΔABC ≅ ΔDEF.
The flaw in the above argument is that it depends on the undefined term
"move". Let "move" (in both Euclidean and Hyperbolic
Geometry) be defined as a function that maps a set of points, P1, P2, P3,
... to P'1, P'2, P'3..., in such a way that for any two points Pn and Pm
of the original set, the distance from Pn to Pm equals the distance from
P'n to P'm. Then, for SAS to hold, it must be that for
any two lines L and L', it is always possible to "move" line L so that
it coincides with L'. This condition is commonly
called the SAS axiom, and it is a axiom of both Euclidean and Hyperbolic
Geometry. [Moise-74]
5.3 Proofs in Hyperbolic Geometry:
Euclid's 5 axioms, the common notions, plus all of his unstated assumptions
together make up the complete axiomatic formation of Euclidean Geometry.
The only difference between the complete axiomatic formation of Euclidean
Geometry and of Hyperbolic Geometry is the Parallel Axiom.
This is a powerful statement. It means that any proof in Euclidean
Geometry which does not use the Parallel Axiom is also a proof in Hyperbolic
Geometry!
Likewise, it means that Euclidean Geometry theorems that require the
Parallel Axiom will be false in Hyperbolic Geometry. A striking example
of this is the Euclidean Geometry theorem that the sum of the angles of
a triangle will always total 180°. Figure 5.4a may help you
recall the proof of this theorem - and see why it is false in Hyperbolic
Geometry.
Figure 5.4a: Proof for m∠A
+ m∠B + m∠C = 180°
In Euclidean Geometry, for any triangle ABC, there
exists a unique parallel to BC that passes through point A. Additionally,
it is a theorem in Euclidean Geometry that when two parallel lines are
cut by a transversal, then the opposite interior angles are congruent;
therefore, ∠NAB ≅ ∠ABC and
∠MAC ≅ ∠ACB. In Hyperbolic Geometry, however, there are an infinite number
of lines that are parallel to BC and pass through point A, yet there does
not exist any line such that both:
∠NAB ≅ ∠ABC and
∠MAC ≅ ∠ACB.
NonEuclid
Home
Next Topic - Area
Copyright©: Joel Castellanos, 1994-2002